Paradoxes of Set Theory
From the paradise, that Cantor created for us, no one can expel us" - declared the great mathematician David Hilbert (1862−1943) regarding the set theory of Georg Cantor (1845−1918). Such was the feeling of delight from the new "toy" among the mathematicians of that time. Set theory was born in 1873 when Cantor introduced the concept of a set and established that the real numbers are uncountable. Initially, the new theory helped solve a number of problems. However, very soon a series of contradictions were revealed in it.
The best-known paradoxes of set theory are
- Russell's paradox
- Cantor's paradox
- Burali-Forti paradox
- Richard's paradox
Consider these paradoxes in more detail.
Russell's Paradox
The Russell's paradox has been discovered in

The Russell's paradox deals with the set of all sets which are not members of themselves. For example, the set of all stars in the universe is not a star itself. Let's denote such a set of all sets by
- Suppose that
is not a member of itself. Then by definition of it must contain itself, that is, must be a member of itself. - Suppose now that
is a member of itself. Then by definition of it must not belong to itself, that is, must not be a member of itself.
In both cases we have a contradiction. This contradiction is just Russell's paradox.
This paradox arises in Cantor's naive set theory which is based on predicate logic. Its formal (simplified) derivation can be obtained as follows:
Within naive set theory, the statement
is true for any predicate or property
Let
This is valid for any set
There is no error in Russell's paradox: it does prove the inconsistency of naive set theory. One of the ways to get rid of the contradiction is to limit the conditions under which sets are formed. The idea is to exclude too large sets like the Russell set
Cantor's Paradox
Cantor's paradox has been discovered by Cantor's himself in

Recall Cantor's theorem which states that, for any set
We denote the set of all sets by
Cantor's paradox demonstrates that the assumption of the existence of a set of all sets leads to a contradiction. Hence, the theory that allows such sets is inconsistent.
Burali-Forti Paradox
This paradox is named after the Italian mathematician Cesare Burali-Forti

Burali-Forti paradox appeared in
According to von Neumann's construction, an ordinal number
where the relation
Let
The ordinal
This contradiction shows that there is no set of all ordinals!
Richard's Paradox
This paradox was first described in

Let's take a natural language, say, English or French (Richard was French). Certain expressions of this language can describe real numbers. For example,
- The Pi number can be described as "the ratio of the circumference of a circle to its diameter.
- The number
can be described as "the real number the integer part of which is and the decimal part is
We arrange all phrases describing real numbers in lexicographic order. As a result, we get an infinite list in which each phrase is mapped to a real number:
Now we apply diagonalization over decimal expansions and construct a new real number
The number
We have considered here only some of the most famous paradoxes. In fact, their list is much wider. For instance, one can mention such paradoxes as the Banach-Tarski paradox, König's paradox, Skolem's paradox, Berry paradox, and others.
In response to set theoretical paradoxes, mathematicians developed axiomatic set theories, which, through various axioms, define what can and cannot be sets. The most common version of the axiomatic set theory is Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory with the Axiom of Choice